Publishing Partner: Cambridge University Press CUP Extra Wiley-Blackwell Publisher Login
amazon logo
More Info


New from Oxford University Press!

ad

Language Planning as a Sociolinguistic Experiment

By: Ernst Jahr

Provides richly detailed insight into the uniqueness of the Norwegian language development. Marks the 200th anniversary of the birth of the Norwegian nation following centuries of Danish rule


New from Cambridge University Press!

ad

Acquiring Phonology: A Cross-Generational Case-Study

By Neil Smith

The study also highlights the constructs of current linguistic theory, arguing for distinctive features and the notion 'onset' and against some of the claims of Optimality Theory and Usage-based accounts.


New from Brill!

ad

Language Production and Interpretation: Linguistics meets Cognition

By Henk Zeevat

The importance of Henk Zeevat's new monograph cannot be overstated. [...] I recommend it to anyone who combines interests in language, logic, and computation [...]. David Beaver, University of Texas at Austin


Query Details


Query Subject:   movement paradoxes
Author:   Carsten Breul
Submitter Email:  click here to access email

Query:   Dear all,

Bresnan (1991, 2001: 16ff.) presents the following examples
and judgments and points out that they pose a problem for
theories of syntax in which it is assumed that the _that_-
clause in front position is moved there from a position in
which it is complement of _of_ /_about_.

(1) a. *He didn't think of that he might be wrong (from id.
1991: 54)
b. That he might be wrong he didn't think of (from ib.)

(2) a. *We talked about that he was sick for days (from ib.
2001: 17)
b. That he was sick we talked about for days (from ib.)

Bresnan calls this observation "movement paradox". (But she
also notes (2001: 24, n. 2) that "in some dialects of
English examples like [{ REF _Ref518219611 }2a] do occur.")

A similar kind of movement paradox seems to hold in the
following examples (from Ward 1986/1988: 192ff.).

(3) a. We had both been thrown into the water to sink or
swim, and SWIM WE HAD - we had swum from very far apar
(attested)
b.They told him that he had to be there all day long and
BE THERE ALL DAY LONG HE HAS! (constructed; Ward's judgment)
c. They provided us with enough beer to drink all day long
and DRINK ALL DAY WE HAVE! (ditto)
d. We had to stand firm, and STAND FIRM WE HAVE! (ditto)

In these cases, reconstitution of the (infinitival?) VP in
front position into post-auxiliar position does not give a
well-formed source for a movement operation.

Can anyone direct me to literature where this problem has
been addressed in a movement-framework (Principles &
Parameters, Minimalist Program)? Or does anyone have an
idea -- which (s)he might want to share -- how this problem
may be approached in a movement-framework? Am I allowed to
assume that the empirical claims (i.e. judgments) presented
above are supported by many native speakers of English?

I would be very grateful for comments, suggestions, hints
etc.

References:

Bresnan, Joan. 1991. "Locative Case vs. Locative Gender".
In: Sutton, Laurel A. & Johnson, Christopher & Shields,
Ruth (eds.): Proceedings of the Seventeenth Annual Meeting
of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, February 15-18, 1991.
Berkeley (CA): Berkeley Linguistics Society. 53-66.

Bresnan, Joan. 2001. Lexical-Functional Syntax. Malden (MA)
& Oxford: Blackwell.

Ward, Gregory L. 1986/1988: The Semantics and Pragmatics of
Preposing. New York & London: Garland.


Dr. Carsten Breul
Universität Dortmund
Institut für Anglistik und Amerikanistik
Emil-Figge-Str. 50
44221 Dortmund
Germany
phone: (0231) 755-2898
e-mail: breul@englisch.fb15.uni-dortmund.de
or
carsten.breul@ruhr-uni-bochum.de


LL Issue: 12.2826
Date posted: 12-Nov-2001



Back

Sums main page